Separation of Powers Approaches
There are two
conflicting judicial philosophies about separation of powers that are
apparent on the Court. The first is formal or
strict separation of powers. Under this view (expressed by
Justice Scalia in his dissent in Morrison
v. Olson), any intrusion, no matter how small or technical, by
one branch into the constitutionally assigned power of another branch,
violates separation of powers. The second is functional
or pragmatic separation of powers. Under this view
(expressed by Justice White in his dissent in Bowsher v. Synar), the court is
concerned with whether there is a genuine threat of encroachment or
aggrandizement of one branch at the expense of another. Applying
this approach, the Court would worry that one branch is increasing the
scope of its authority unreasonably and disturbing the delicate balance
among the three coequal branches by becoming too powerful (Bowsher v. Synar and concern that
by making and executing the laws, Congress was exercising too much
power under the Deficit Reduction Act).
Justice Scalia (dissenting in Morrison
v. Olson):
Article II, § 1, cl. 1, of the Constitution provides:
The executive Power shall be vested in a President of the
United States.
As I described at the outset of this opinion, this does not
mean some
of the executive power, but all of the executive power. It seems to me,
therefore, that the decision of the Court of Appeals invalidating the
present statute must be upheld on fundamental separation of powers
principles if the following two questions are answered affirmatively:
(1) Is the conduct of a criminal prosecution (and of an investigation
to decide whether to prosecute) the exercise of purely executive power?
(2) Does the statute deprive the President of the United States of
exclusive control over the exercise of that power? Surprising to say,
the Court appears to concede an affirmative answer to both questions,
but seeks to avoid the inevitable conclusion that, since the statute
vests some purely executive power in a person who is not the President
of the United States, it is void.
Justice White (dissenting in
Bowsher v. Synar):
I cannot concur in the Court's action. Like the Court, I will
not
purport to speak to the wisdom of the policies incorporated in the
legislation the Court invalidates; that is a matter for the Congress
and the Executive, both of which expressed their assent to the statute
barely half a year ago. I will, however, address the wisdom of the
Court's willingness to interpose its distressingly formalistic view of
separation of powers as a bar to the attainment of governmental
objectives through the means chosen by the Congress and the President
in the legislative process established by the Constitution.
The Court's decision rests on a feature of the legislative
scheme that
is of minimal practical significance and that presents no substantial
threat to the basic scheme of separation of powers. In attaching
dispositive significance to what should be regarded as a triviality,
the Court neglects what has in the past been recognized as a
fundamental principle governing consideration of disputes over
separation of powers:
"The actual art of governing under our Constitution does not
and cannot
conform to judicial definitions of the power of any of its branches
based on isolated clauses or even single Articles torn from context.
While the Constitution diffuses power the better to secure liberty, it
also contemplates that practice will integrate the dispersed powers
into a workable government." Youngstown
Sheet & Tube Co. v.
Sawyer, 343 U.S. 579, 635 (1952) (Jackson, J. concurring).